1.3 — Preferences — Appendix
Strict vs. Weak Preferences
We have defined preferences as being strictly one of the following possibilities:
( is strictly preferred over b) ( is strictly preferred over a) (indifferent between a)
You can also have weak preferences, such as
( is at least as preferred as (or “weakly preferred over” ) ( is at least as preferred as (or “weakly preferred over” )
These are more technically complete, but it is much more simple for us to focus on strong preferences, and we don’t lose much by doing so.
Assumptions of “Well-behaved Preferences”
Reflexivity : any bundle is at least as preferred as itself
Completeness : any two bundles can be compared
Transitivity : rankings are logically consistent:
- If
and , then
Are these good assumptions? As you will find typical in economics, very often yes, sometimes no! See the growing field of Behavioral economics for interesting anomalies and exceptions to our assumptions.
Assumptions of “Well-behaved Indifference Curves”
Like preferences, we make 4 major assumptions about indifference curves to describe the normal case. In fact, many of these assumptions are derived from the assumptions we made above about well-behaved preferences
- We can always draw indifference curves: two bundles can always be ranked
Every possible bundle (point on graph) is on an indifference curve.
Of course, this means that this entire graph is full of indifference curves - every single possible point is on some indifference curve (and this whole graph would just be a solid block of black). Naturally, it’s pointless to draw all the indifference curves, we just want to show a few to make our analysis meaningful. But the general idea comes from assumption 2 of preferences: any two bundles can be compared, as we can compare two points on this graph and make a judgment.
- Indifference curves are monotonic, which means practically that “more is preferred to less”
For any bundle
Here’s a challenge: what would indifference curves look like if one of the axes contained a bad, rather than a good? In this case, we would violate the assumption of monotonicity!
- Indifference curves are convex, which means in practice that “averages are preferred to extremes”
From experience, people generally prefer variety in their consumption. Rather than having one bundle that is “extreme” (a lot of one good and little or none of another), they tend to prefer a bundle with a better “mix” or “balance” of some of both goods.
Take our example from class, hunting for apartments. Apartment
Mathematically, this feature is because indifference curves are normally convex. A function is convex when a line connecting any two points on the function lies above the function itself. Check the math review guide for more information.
Here’s a challenge: what would non-convex (e.g. concave) curves look like, and what preferences would cause that situation?
- Indifference curves can never cross because we have assumed that preferences are transitive.
Suppose two curves crossed, as the ones below:
- On the blue indifference curve,
- On the orange indifference curve
- But clearly
- Preferences are not transitive!
Steepness & Indifference Curves for Neutrals
The Steepness of indifference curves tells us how consumers trade off between goods.
Perfectly vertical curves (left)
Perfectly horizontal curves (right)
We can look at less extreme cases:
On the left graph, the flatter curve implies the person is willing to give up only a few Downloads to obtain more Tickets (and vice versa).
On the right graph, the steeper curve implies the person is willing to give up a lot Downloads to obtain more Tickets (and vice versa).
Derivation of MRS Equation (as ratio of marginal utilities)
Consider a movement along an indifference curve, how would this change affect utility? There will be a change in
Notice rise over run,
Utility Functions and PMTs
Two utility functions
The following utility functions express the same preferences:
A positive monotonic transformation (PMT) transforms quantities such that the rank order of the quantities is preserved.
- Examples:
Any PMT of a utility function contains the same preferences!
Graphing Indifference Curves
I will not ask you to formally graph indifference curves (just roughly sketch them where appropriate). If you wanted to graph them, and express them in a graphable (slope-intercept form) equation, simply solve for the good on the vertical axis.
Example: Suppose we have a typical1 indifference curve for apples
Each indifference curve (or contour) is one level of utility (all points on the curve give a specific level of utility). So, set that level of utility equal to some constant,
Then, if we are putting
This is the general equation for all indifference curves of this utility function: each utility level (value of
Utility Functions for Perfect Substitutes
Perfect substitutes produce straight lines for indifference curves. A straight line has a constant slope, which is interpretted as the MRS being constant - you should always be willing to substitute between the two goods at the same rate. The utility function looks like:
Where each
Notice, having some of one good and none of the other still provides positive utility (unlike utility functions where the quantities of goods are multiplied!). This is precisely because of the substitutability between the goods!
Example
Consider 1-Liter bottles of Coke
The relative weights here are 1 for 1-Liter bottles and 2 for 2-Liter bottles, because 2-Liter bottles are “worth” twice as much for you (it takes two 1-Liter bottles to match a 2-Liter bottle!).
Utility Functions for Perfect Complements
Perfect complements produce right angles for indifference curves. This is technically not a mathematical function, since each
Where each
The marginal rate of substitution alternates between
Example
Consider consuming hot dogs
Having 2 hot dogs and 3 buns only yields a utility of 2. Having 3 hot dogs and 2 buns also only yields a utility of 2.
Cobb-Douglas Functions
Cobb-Douglas functions (both for utility and production) are one of the most common functional forms in economics. Despite their somewhat frightening presence on the surface, they have very neat mathematical properties, and have been empirically useful as well. A Cobb-Douglas function (for utility) looks like:
MRS and Positive Monotonic Transformations
The marginal rate of substitution, using the above equation is:
Using logarithms, we can take a positive monotonic transformation of the original utility function
The MRS using the logarithmic form is:
Which of course, is the same, because we know any positive monotonic transformation of a utility function preserves the same preferences!
EXAMPLE
Find the marginal rate of substitution for the utility function:
First, recognize that square roots are equivalent to saying
Note we could find this equivalently again by taking logs of the original utility function.
Which again, gives us the same marginal rate of substitution.
Footnotes
Cobb-Douglas!↩︎